The
Star Larvae Hypothesis
Phylogeny, the Arrow of EvolutionComparative genomics makes evolution look like a developmental program.
In the scientific account, evolution is shaped by natural selection, which acts on the variation that occurs among individuals in the local population of a species. Environments "select" for survival those individuals endowed by nature with a "selective advantage," that is, with adaptive traits that enable it to survive and beget fertile, viable offspring. Individuals selected by the environment to survive and bear progeny skew the genetic profile of generations down the line. As a result, successive generations of a species might bear little resemblance to their ancestors, because they represent only that slice of the original gene pool, supplemented by mutations, horizontal gene transfer, and possibly other sources of genetic novelty, that possessed the characteristics necessary for survival and reproduction. For generations sufficiently far down the line, the genome of any descendant species is up for grabs. Its makeup will depend on the particular demands made by the environment, which can change significantly as environments themselves change.
No amphibian hatchling can mature into a wolf, but amphibians as a class can sprout a family tree that eventually includes wolves and many other unamphibious descendants. The divergences can become so pronounced, that humankind for the longest time failed to develop any widely held concept of species descent. However, as the theory of evolution gained currency, hypotheses arose that sought to relate phylogeny and ontogeny in meaningful ways. As different as they are in scale, both can appear to be processes of development. Both are certainly processes of, in Darwin's words, descent with modification. One influential unification of the two concepts was the "biogenetic law" of German biologist Ernst Haekel in the nineteenth century. Haekel's alliterative law, "Ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny," was widely adopted as a scientific principle, its influence reaching well into the twentieth century. Haeckel proposed that a complex organism passes through the stages of its ancestral phylogeny, through the various steps from simple unicellular creature through stages that repeat its evolutionary history. Does Evolution Anticipate Descendant Species?The ontogeny of an individual organism appears to be an example of ends being imminent in a natural process—that is, of a natural teleology. But, in the received view, ontogeny is embedded in the larger context of nonteleological, unprogrammed phylogeny. The star larvae hypothesis challenges this view. The hypothesis reconceptualizes the relationship between ontogeny and phylogeny. It locates phylogeny—biological life’s evolutionary history—within an overarching ontogeny—the stellar life cycle—making the former subordinate to the latter. It inverts the received relationship between ontogeny and phylogeny; it assigns to evolution an ontogenetic plan.
1. Junk DNA. This is not a particularly new discovery. It’s been known for some time that all species carry around a lot of junk, DNA that appears to lie dormant or to code for RNA that lies dormant. What aspect of evolution theory predicts that long stretches of irrelevant DNA would coast along inside organisms, seemingly contributing nothing to their survivability? Nobody saw it coming. It was an empirical surprise. But in the context of ontogeny, the development of organisms, it is exactly what is to be expected. Each cell in the body of a complex organism inherits the same genes from the ancestral zygote, the original fertilized ovum. But, despite all possessing the same genes, brain, liver, kidney, and skin cells, for example, distinguish themselves phenotypically. However, because they all inherit the same genes, there must be a lot of junk DNA in each type of cell. Brain cells don’t need genes that function uniquely in liver cells, nor do kidney cells need genes that function uniquely in skin cells. But all the cells inherit all those genes from their common ancestor, the zygote, whether they need them or not. When it comes to cell types in a body, an invariant genetic inheritance necessarily is the case, with lots of junk in each cell as a result. Ontogeny demonstrates that diverse morphologies, or phenotypes, need not correspond to any proportionate diversity of genotype. “Adaptive radiation” of cell types in a body proceeds just fine without genetic variation. Evolution now appears to operate similarly. 2. Conservation of DNA. Genetic material across species, though not invariant, turns out to be much less variable than observable differences among species would suggest. DNA is highly conserved across species. In their article, Regulating Evolution (Scientific American, May 2010) researchers Sean B. Carroll, Benjamin Prud’homme, and Nicolas Gompel comment, "For a long time, scientists certainly expected the anatomical differences among animals to be reflected in clear differences among the contents of their genomes. When we compare mammalian genomes such as those of the mouse, rat, dog, human and chimpanzee, however, we see that their respective gene catalogues are remarkably similar. [. . . .] When comparing mouse and human genomes, for example, biologists are able to indentify a mouse counterpart of at least 99 percent of all our genes."The perplexed authors elaborate on the new findings: ". . . to our surprise, it has turned out that differences in appearance are deceiving: very different animals have very similar sets of genes." "The preservation of coding sequences over evolutionary time is especially puzzling when one considers the genes involved in body building and body patterning." "The discovery that body-building proteins are even more alike on average than other proteins was especially intriguing because of the paradox it seemed to pose: animals as different as a mouse and an elephant are shaped by a common set of very similar, functionally indistinguishable body-building proteins."Surprise? Puzzling? Paradox? Why does evolution theory suffer so many bouts of the unexpected now that genomes are yielding their secrets? If the received theory of evolution were solid, wouldn’t new genetic details have slots waiting for them in it? Shouldn’t new genetic data bolster the theory, rather than generate surprises, puzzles and paradoxes for it to resolve? Why didn’t evolution theorists predict that phenotypic and genotypic differences across species would turn out to be so disproportionate, that so few genes would produce so many species? Nobody saw it coming. It was an empirical surprise.
Now, due to the work of Carroll, Prud’homme, Gompel and others, it looks like evolution uses regulatory genes in the same way. Instead of spinning off variant cell types, the cycling on and off of genetic switches in the context of evolution spins off variant species. This discovery, of the importance of genetic switches in evolution and its helping to account for the low level of genetic diversity across species, was an empirical surprise. Nobody saw it coming. The explanatory power of this discovery has produced a new discipline within evolutionary biology, called evolutionary developmental biology, or evo-devo, a science that gives regulatory genes a starring role in evolution. Traditionally, evolution theory cast organisms in the passive role of protoplasmic clay being shaped by exogenous environmental influences. Evo-devo underscores the importance of endogenous influences on evolution, and thereby support the case that evolution is a developmental process. 4. Anticipatory genes. A new organism, a zygote, a fertilized egg carries many genes that ride along unexpressed—until they are needed by descendant cell types. The zygote anticipates, in its genetic catalog, the genes that remote descendant cells will need, even if those genes contribute nothing to the survival of the zygote itself or its immediate descendants. The zygote divides into two cells, and the two into four, and the four into eight, and so on. The cells that make up these early stages are said to be totipotent cells—they can bear descendants of any cell type. Later, after a degree of specialization, cells become pluripotent—they can give rise to several cell types, though not to all. And the specialization continues from there, with descendants inheriting from their ancestors the specialized genes they need, along with the rest of the genome. This is to be expected in the context of a developing organism. But it turns out that ancient species also carry genes that seem to anticipate the needs of descendants. A news article in Nature covering the sequencing of the genome of the Great Barrier Reef sponge Amphimedon queenslandica, reveals that the hoary creatures harbor a “tookit” of metazoan genes: "The genome also includes analogues of genes that, in organisms with a neuromuscular system, code for muscle tissue and neurons."A curious finding. The article continues: "According to Douglas Erwin, a palaeobiologist at the Smithsonian Institution in Washington DC, such complexity indicates that sponges must have descended from a more advanced ancestor than previously suspected. 'This flies in the face of what we think of early metazoan evolution,' says Erwin." "Charles Marshall, director of the University of California Museum of Paleontology in Berkeley, agrees. 'It means there was an elaborate machinery in place that already had some function,' he says. 'What I want to know now is what were all these genes doing prior to the advent of sponges.'"The conundrum for normal evolution theory is clear. But, rather than propose that the genes needed by organisms with neuromuscular systems are in the sponge for the anticipatory purpose of providing those genes to descendants who will need them, the scientists invent an imaginary ancestor of the sponge that needed the genes. But the ghostly ancestor would have had to have arisen within a very narrow window. Fossil evidence of sponges goes back 650 million years; it constitutes, the authors note, “the oldest evidence for metazoans (multicellular animals) on Earth.” So, what use would any species even more primitive than sponges have for the neuromuscular genes? Nobody saw it coming. It was an empirical surprise. But the sponge genome is only one example. Research is finding case after case of ancestral species that harbor genes essential for remote descendants. Another example: It turns out that a species of unicellular protozoan carries genes essential for metabolic processes specific to metazoans. The researchers who discovered the surprise genes and published their data (PNAS – 2010 107 (22) 10142-10147) explain, "One of the most important cell adhesion mechanisms for metazoan development is integrin-mediated adhesion and signaling. The integrin adhesion complex mediates critical interactions between cells and the extracellular matrix, modulating several aspects of cell physiology. To date this machinery has been considered strictly metazoan specific. [. . . .] Unexpectedly, we found that core components of the integrin adhesion complex are encoded in the genome of the apusozoan protist Amastigomonas sp., and therefore their origins predate the divergence of Opisthokonta, the clade that includes metazoans and fungi. [. . . .] Our data highlight the fact that many of the key genes that had formerly been cited as crucial for metazoan origins have a much earlier origin." (emphasis added) And the surprises just keep coming. A news release (11/24/2005) issued by the journal Trends in Genetics announces that "Corals and sea anemones (the flowers of the sea), long regarded as merely simple sea-dwelling animals, turn out to be more genetically complex than first realised. They have just as many genes as most mammals, including humans, and many of the genes that were thought to have been "invented" in vertebrates are actually very old and are present in these "simple" animals." The full
text of the release is available at http://www.sars.no/resear
ch/technau_Science.pdf. Newer
(2007) sequencing and analysis results corroborate the anemone anomalies. These
and other phylogenetically anomalous results of genomic analysis are collected
at http://www.panspermia.org/oldgenes.htm.
This page of Brig Klyce’s "Cosmic
Ancestry" web site includes commentary on the relevance of these
findings to panspermia.
To propose that evolution is programmed in a way similar to that in which the development of an organism is programmed is anathema to current evolution theory. The current theory has no room for teleology. But the new research findings point directly to such a conclusion. As happens in the history of science, scientists have to decide whether to stretch the normal paradigm to try to cover a growing collection of anomalous data or to construct a new paradigm based on the data. If discoveries of evolutionarily anticipatory DNA are not taken as evidence of a evolutionary program, then what justifies assigning a program to ontogeny?A complex organism begins life as a single cell of a morphologically generic sort. The fertilized egg cells of seahorses, hummingbirds, and humans, for example, are phenotypically indistinguishable. The all look alike. The fertilized egg divides into two cells, then into four, and so on, until enough cells exist for the cellular collective to initiate a specialization of labor. The various types of cells compete and cooperate to acquire the resources that they need to survive, and their collective labors constitute the physiology of the embryo that their bodies, in aggregate, constitute. As the process continues, the distinctive features of the species emerge. At some point during embryological development, a cell that is only a progenitor of a liver cell gives rise to a true liver cell; a cell that is a progenitor of a neuron gives rise to a neuron, and so on. Embryonic cells give rise to specific morphological types that behave in specific ways in their interlocking niches within the somatic ecology of the organism's physical being. Is this process of diversification teleological or Darwinian?
Consider the counterintuitive argument: Insofar as there is variation among the individuals in the population of any particular cell type in the body of a complex organism, and insofar as not every cell survives to contribute its genetic predispositions to the next generation, there is a natural selection among cells during ontogeny. This thought experiment—fitting ontogenetic cellular differentiation into a model of Darwinian phylogeny—underscores an early and continuing criticism of Darwinian logic, namely that it is tautological. When formulated as "survival of the fittest" the doctrine of natural selection identifies the fittest organisms as those that survive and the survivors as those most fit. Ontogeny can also be seen as a phylogeny, a "cytophylogeny," in which a common ancestral starting point—a fertilized ovum—begets successive generations of increasingly diverse descendant forms. Imagine the cells of a complex organism, having developed their own theory of evolution, marveling at the blind workings of mutation and natural selection that turned their common ancestor—the original ovum—into the diversity of interdependent cellular species in which they find themselves enmeshed. Fitness selects the survivors, they would say, as demonstrated by their survival! We would understand that these scientifically minded cells have missed the boat, that they live by a developmental program and that they are mistaken when they explain their situation in nonteleological terms. Their thinking, however, would be consistent with modern science's theory of human descent. The star larvae hypothesis argues that human beings have made the same mistake as these cells, in believing that nonteleological processes delivered them from their remote ancestors. The
late Harvard paleontologist Stephen Jay Gould accounted for the apparent
progress of evolutionary change with the metaphor of "the drunkard’s
walk." In this thought experiment you must imagine a drunkard staggering
along a wall. He ventures varying distances from the wall as he makes
his way along it. The distance from the wall at any particular instant
is just whatever it is. An increase in average distance over time is merely
a function of time passing. The more time that passes, the greater the
number of opportunities for the drunk to stumble even farther from the
wall than he or she previously had ventured. Increasing distance from
the wall corresponds to the increasing complexity, with the wall representing
the unicellular limit of biological simplicity. By this metaphor the apparent
increase in complexity of organisms over evolutionary time, which suggests
a direction to evolution, is better understood as the undirected spread
of mere variation. Increases in variation are sufficient to product increases
in complexity. Gould lays out this model of pseudoprogress in Full
House Philosophers
Kim Sterelny and Paul E. Griffiths, in Sex
and Death: An Introduction to Philosophy of Biology
Again, when this line of thinking is applied to ontogeny, the shoe fits. We can ask whether cellular differentiation during the ontogenetic development of an organism the result of wholly undirected, stochastic mechanisms that merely increase variance among cell types. The received view says no; explanations from phylogeny are inadequate to account for ontogeny. But the parallels are stiking: Some cell types, the early undifferentiated types of the blastula, for example, go extinct during human ontogeny. Though, some ancestral types persist, in the form of adult stem cells. And bacteria dominate the environment, comprising 90 percent of the cells in a human body. So why assume an ontogenetic program? Doesn't Gould's model equally well explain the diversification of cells during ontogeny as it does the diversification of species during phylogeny? Empirically, the two processes are of a kind: multiform descent from a common ancestor. To clarify: The star larvae hypothesis does not argue that ontogeny is a stochastic process that merely increases variance among cell types, but accepts the received view that ontogeny follows an inherent program. But it rejects the received view when it comes to phylogeny, which, it argues, also follows an inherent program. The applicability of phylogeny's supposed mechanisms to account for ontogeny is meant as a reductio ad absurdum of the received view regarding phylogeny; i.e., if phylogenetic theory has such vast explanatory power, why assume programming anywhere? Cells cooperate and compete in an organism, and organisms cooperate and compete in an ecosystem. If we will not reduce ontogeny to nonteleological processes, then perhaps we can consider that science has erred in reducing phylogeny to nonteleological processes. The Great Chain of Being
The Chain of Being represents a longitudinal section through a temporal progression—a developmental sequence that leads from the terrestrial to the extraterrestrial. The Chain was conceived of at a time when Creation was regarded as static, and the Chain provided a cross section of the whole structure. Once we assign the evolution of species to a subordinate position within the overarching ontogeny of the stellar life cycle, we effectively resurrect the Chain of Being, but in an ecological context. Evolution is the metamorphosis of stages in the life cycle of a genus of organism—the stellar organism. The apparent directionlessness of evolution is replaced by a processional sequence that, when viewed in a longitudinal section, takes the form of the Great Chain of Being. The intuition behind the Chain was essentially right, it just failed to take into account the underlying dynamic, temporal process.
The Star Larvae Hypothesis: Stars constitute a genus of organism. The stellar life cycle includes a larval phase. Biological life constitutes the larval phase of the stellar life cycle. Elaboration: The hypothesis presents a teleological model of nature, in which
Home | Blog | About | Videos | Contact | Text Copyright ©2004-2017 Advanced Theological Systems. All Rights Reserved. Privacy Statement: We use third-party advertising companies to serve ads when you visit our website. These companies may use information (not including your name, address, email address, or telephone number) about your visits to this and other websites in order to provide advertisements about goods and services of interest to you. If you would like more information about this practice and to know your choices about not having this information used by these companies, visit the Google ad and content network privacy policy. |